Some Further Discussion on Piercello's Proposal

Piercello asked me to clarify the boundary between strict logic and the kind of practical logics we find in ethics (like the use of logic in rhetoric). I thought the answer was worth a separate post.
I'm delighted to host a discussion like this one. It's an excellent use of our limited time on earth to wrestle with these high questions.

The boundary between strict logic and non-strict logic (including but not limited to rhetorical logic) is bright-line, and indeed already expressed in our discussion. It has to do with what kinds of objects the logic is treating. Strict logic treats logical objects, i.e., objects that are internally consistent throughout.

Objects in strict logic include universals, variables, and constants. Universals are true universals (usually formalized as capital letters these days, like "F"). A constant is an individual (usually 'a, b, c...' from the front of the alphabet); a variable (usually 'x, y, z') is a set of particulars that can range over many individuals, so that you can speak using variables about what it means for particulars to instantiate the universal. So if "F" is "is a raven," then "Fx" is "anything that is a raven," and "Fa" is "a, which is a raven." Expressed in more Platonic terms, "F" is a way of referring to the form of ravenness; Fx refers to all objects that instantiate this form; Fa refers to one particular object that instantiates the form.

However, as Aristotle points out at the beginning of the [Nicomachean] ethics, we never encounter any of these things in real life. His account of why objects don't perfectly instantiate Platonic forms differs from mine; he thought that practical objects, being made of matter, didn't perfectly instantiate the forms because of the potential necessary for matter which was never quite fully actualized into the pure activity of the form. I've explained that I think the real reason is that we shift from logical objects to analogies between physical objects that really aren't 'alike throughout' in the way that logical objects by their nature are.

Note then that Kant is not really doing strict logic at any point in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Because this is groundwork for a project in the practical world, he is always dealing with ethical objects rather than strict logical objects. Kant is really unhappy with Aristotle's approach, which I mentioned above. What Aristotle says is this (EN 1.3):

"Our discussion will be adequate if it has as much clearness as the subject-matter admits of, for precision is not to be sought for alike in all discussions, any more than in all the products of the crafts. Now fine and just actions, which political science investigates, admit of much variety and fluctuation of opinion, so that they may be thought to exist only by convention, and not by nature. And goods also give rise to a similar fluctuation because they bring harm to many people; for before now men have been undone by reason of their wealth, and others by reason of their courage. We must be content, then, in speaking of such subjects and with such premisses to indicate the truth roughly and in outline, and in speaking about things which are only for the most part true and with premisses of the same kind to reach conclusions that are no better."

Kant does not like the idea that we cannot be precise in our ethical conclusions, and is trying hard to figure out a way around the problem that will allow for clear, precise, rational ethical decision. His move is to reach for universals not as forms, but in terms of generalizing situations to see if you can come to general principles (i.e. what he calls 'universal laws') that govern all different instances of a problem. (It will turn out you really can't, because problems don't instantiate singularly; usually a real ethical dilemma is a nest of different problems, where the general principles are in conflict. But set that aside.)

I recommend Kant because his project seems to me to be allied to yours in important ways. It is definitely not exactly the same, though. You are also wrestling with this issue of how to persuade people to behave in more rational ways. Like Kant, you need to get people to accept standards that are alien or foreign to them currently. Kant's introducing several concepts that are brand new, like the categorical imperative; no one has ever heard this terminology before at the time he's publishing this groundbreaking work. So he has to persuade people (rhetoric) that this is a sensible way to talk, as well as that it can solve some of the problems of ethics (rhetorical logic).

Note, though, that he is not really at any point engaged in strict logic. He is trying as hard as he can to find something analogous to a logical object in practical life. The universals he's reaching for with his 'universal laws' aren't logical universals, but broad analogies under which many different practical problems might fall.

As a result, the sandwich you describe isn't quite there. Rather, he is trying to shoehorn analogy into logic as much as can be done. I think Kant believes he's successful, which enables him in the wider Metaphysics of Morals (written many years after the Groundwork, by the way) to declare his conclusions with much more firmness than they have proven to deserve (e.g., that any just society must have a sovereign individual who is immune to the laws; that marriage can only be a union of exactly two persons of the opposite sex, and that absolutely all societies must introduce legal marriage in precisely this form; that masturbation is necessarily worse than suicide; etc).

That said, I also think you can learn the rules of strict logic without in any way adopting the consensus that they are the right way to proceed. Most everyone who engages in the practice seriously, including myself, develops a critique of parts of it. That's one of the most interesting aspects of the study of logic. There is a rhetorical aspect to such criticisms, in that we are trying to persuade each other that our approach to wrestling with the problem we've encountered with the system is better than other methods. But it's not necessary to learning the system; all that you have to do to learn the system is learn it, not consent to it.

The closest thing I think you can say is that you have to learn the rules of a game to play the game. But it's still not rhetoric; it just looks like rhetoric because we typically learn it from someone else. Imagine (here's a Kantian exercise) a man who was somehow born and raised by wolves, but in his adulthood began to try to work out the rules of logic. He might come up with different ways of solving particular problems, just as in math the Japanese have developed a different way of doing multiplication than Westerners. But because strict logic like* math has an objective standard, whatever approaches he developed could be found to be valid or invalid, complete or incomplete, independently of ever discussing them with anyone. The objective standard is provided by logic itself: some approaches to logic work, and some do not.

It's sticky, trying to deal with the hinge between these models -- which can somehow be objectively tested against themselves, that itself a philosophical difficulty -- and the way the models apply to reality. Somehow they do, even though the kinds of objects involved in math/logic are not what we encounter, we can use math and logic predicatively with a lot of success. Why the success is even possible is a problem, given the incompatibility of the kinds of objects involved; why the success applies only imperfectly is another problem.

If I've given you serious problems, though, I'm doing my proper work as a philosopher.

* "like math" is itself problematic philosophically; there's a huge debate as to whether logic is in fact a subset of math, or indeed whether math is actually a subset of logic, or if they are simply similar fields. This is non-resolved after 2,000 years of discussion.

28 comments:

Ymar Sakar said...

Kant channeled two of those conclusions. It is notthat hecreated justifications and that ledto conclusions. He was given conclusions by divine revelation and needed the human logic rationale for how or why.

As for math, two humans could be uding base 3 and base 4 such that 2 plus 2 is not 4. It is 11 base 3. And 10 base 4.

So multiplication rules matter less than the unspoken, shadows of premise, axiom, and a priori

Grim said...

As regards base 3 or 4, yes; but the point is that this difference is not rhetorical. If you were raised by wolves and yet developed in your mind a functional base 3 mathematics, should you later meet a Western mathematician, you could compare your systems and realize that the difference in your approach lay in the base you were using.

It's not rhetoric, in other words: the task is not to persuade each other of a consensus position about the base way of doing it. What your discussion would reveal was that both systems worked; developing a consensus approach was not necessary. This is because both systems are based on some feature of objective reality that makes mathematics functional. You might succeed in persuading the Western mathematician to abandon base 10, or he might persuade you, but it isn't necessary that either of you should persuade the other to recognize that -- once appropriate adjustments were made -- you were getting the same results.

ymarsakar said...

It's not rhetoric, in other words: the task is not to persuade each other of a consensus position about the base way of doing it.

I am not saying it is rhetoric. That's another person's subject matter.

The consensus position is not something people use as persuasion. It is something they are born with or raised with, a set of identity beliefs that they never challenge. A priori premises that cannot or will not be challenged because the user does not even know they are there.

So for example, if a person knows they are using another base system, then they would conclude that the reason they disagree with foreigner A, is that they are using different bases. However, if nobody there understands what a base is.. then they would assume they are talking to an idiot or that everybody's math is wrong.

This is seen in Flat Earth Theory vs Heliocentricism.

Good old 1984's author whatshisname, even wrote an article about it.

Piercello said...

Let me attempt to bridge this gap.

By my lights, ANY such terminological convention, whether one is born into it or adopts in for practical reasons (such as easier communication with an established discipline), is by nature a pre-existing rhetorical consensus, in which the terminological battles have already been fought and settled.

Grim is saying that this is (in effect) a distinction without a difference, while to Ymar the distinction matters a bit more.

Does this work?

To me, both are skins of words stretched over a wordless logic. I am more interested in that interior logical structure than its surface verbal description, although that is slowly changing as I flounder about trying to communicate what I have found.

And again, here by "logic" I am talking about unchanging structural/relational principles, such as those that remain constant across all of human decision-making, even the irrational parts. I think this is compatible with Grim's framing of strict logic.

We know that the irrational part must be there, from constructing obviously false statements such as these:

"Everyone agrees that my side is the one that is rational, and theirs is the one that is irrational;"

"No one in the history of humankind has ever sincerely changed a deeply held, 'core identity' position;"

"No one has ever reasoned themselves out of doing something, and then just gone and done it anyway."


So, the challenge is to rationally reverse-engineer a set of unchanging principles that accurately describe what IS going on in the universal logic of human decision-making, and then put them to good use.

[The reason we HAVE to do it, now, is that accelerating technology has already rendered all "us/them" forms of politics obsolete. Our societal problems will remain intractable, and explosively so, unless we can express their solutions in terms of knowable human similarities, rather than as functions of our real and imagined differences. But that is a different part of my argument.]

Ymar, with respect to the unpersuasive differences we see in clashing belief systems, would you agree that finding a consensus "that there is no consensus" might itself have strategic implications?

As in, "we agree that our problem is that we disagree, so what do we do about it?"

Can our view of such a disagreement be changed from "something that must be eliminated" to "an immovable constraint that must be engineered around?"

This is why I am more interested in tracing the logical _processes_ by which beliefs are formed, maintained, experienced, and defended than I am in pinning down the specific _content_ of those beliefs.

I think my approach is more likely to have strong practical applications.

ymarsakar said...

As in, "we agree that our problem is that we disagree, so what do we do about it?"

The key difference in our positions or at least my position here, is on epistemology and knowledge. Logical rules only work given the axioms and a prioris used, but when people use unchallenged and unknown a prioris, this creates a flaw in the Matrix. Or perhaps it is a feature of the Matrix, same as Plato's Cave. Perhaps it would be beneficial to go over what Plato's Cave revelation was about.

So it is not that we agree that our problem is that we disagree, but that I point out that nobody even knows what the problem is or that they have a disagreement on a central axiom several logical steps removed from the actual argument.

This is similar to Alcoholic denial that there is a problem. Yes, when a person accepts there might be a problem, AAA can do something. But if they refuse to accept there is a problem? Then there is no problem.

This has to do with the entire universe, humanity, and its logical materialism. The ability to use the mind to perceive physical reality as reality.

ymarsakar said...

This is why I am more interested in tracing the logical _processes_ by which beliefs are formed, maintained, experienced, and defended than I am in pinning down the specific _content_ of those beliefs.


For that, it would be of more benefit to deal with scenarios such as Flat Earth Theory vs Heliocentricism (current status quo scientific dogma or consensus, aka scientism the church of white lab coats).

The fact that few if anybody is doing so... isn't that itself a Big Hint as to what type of logic, if any, is being used to process beliefs?

ymarsakar said...

What Grim seems to be utilizing from my pov is that if two different factions could talk about their differences and commonalities, then they could unify and create something of lasting value.

This is reflected in his historical posts in the past (assuming there is a past), concerning Left vs Right distinctions. That is not that far from P's own value statements here concerning experience/defending.

My counter statement was stated above.

This is cheating in epistemology, because I am not using the statements here and the thoughts presented in words to create a theory and to then justify the theory. I am receiving the conclusion directly, and then reverse engineering it to a reason/logic. That is feasible for those that can directly pick up the intent behind communication as well as the range of human emotions.

This breaks the rules of epistemology. The fact that it works, also breaks people's minds, but that is another issue.

For those that aren't trained in formal logic... well, suffice it to say, that to a person that lives in linear time, the idea of entities interfering with this world that is outside of time/causality, is seen as a cheat/exploit/rule breaking. That is only an analogy and not yet a parable cause I lack time now.

ymarsakar said...

A simple analogy would be American union fees vs Chinese union fees.

On the surface... it appears similar yes. In reality, the rules of America are non existent in China. Thus to America, China is "breaking fair trade". To China, America is the rich father/grand father that doesn't want anybody else in the human clan to get any better or richer.

In order to perceive the differences between 2 viewpoints, one must adopt those 2 viewpoints. Walk in their shoes. But few actually understand how hard that is.

Piercello said...

Here's where I suggest that I already know what type of logic it is, I'm just struggling to find a way to explain my findings within the constraints of written communication.

Meanwhile, back to your previous comment.

Pursued to its logical extent, the major problem with epistemological barfights is that everyone involved is bringing their own personal, and therefore very probably unique, set of emotionally attached axioms to the battle.

This is a large part of why battles over "who is right" are futile, especially in politics. It is also probably why you haven't yet persuaded Grim. 8-)

That's why I am playing a meta-logical game: "WHY don't we agree over who is right?" What are the hidden rules that govern the emotional persistence of such disagreements?

The payoff would go something like this:

If one can rationally map the universal (but non-rational) logic of human decision-making, then one can also map the emergent societal consequences of everyone making decisions in the same way over time.

And from there, from that knowledge of the underlying social physics, one can engineer a thriving, healthy society that actually works, instead of driving it off the cliff yet again with the best of intentions.

If you understand the rules, then it becomes possible to play to win.

Piercello said...

I should clarify this.

I don't mean, "how should we change our decision-making to fix things," I mean, "given the unchangeable way we make our decisions, how should we proceed for good results?"

Ymar Sakar said...

I do not seek to persuadr grim because i am not using rhetoric. That is another persons subject not mine.

People are attached to conclusions, which are attached to pet theories and axioms. But they can give up their axioms and theories if they can keep the conclusions.

Epistemological debates centet around how logic players know things to be true. It is not about being right but rather about there even being a right and wrong. Ehat if everyone is right. And what if everyone is wrong.

Society of humans do not work because of the meta physics i detailed before as a result of divine revelation or download.

That is not a kind of rhetoric.

I would dispute the inability to change how we make decisions. Infact i brought up 3 or 5 examples. Me and kant vs grim and p. Or platos cave vs modern physica of 20th century anti quantum

Piercello said...

Ymar,

This is a helpful conversation to me. Let me see if I can lay out the hybrid sort of Epistemic quest I have in mind.

It is part "working backwards to logically justify a pre-existing conclusion," as you have brought up, and part "reasoning forward from that reverse-engineered foundation to discover hidden logical truths that go beyond the original problem," as Grim has talked about.

Where that hybrid approach sits on the spectrum of standard epistemic approaches, I don't know, but there it is.

Humanity's classic social problem (premise, axiom) is self-evident: people disagree over too many basic issues to let society run well. Shared trust is low and dropping, while the stakes (and tempers) are rising.

By itself, this problem is not a premise that supports useful rational argument, nor obvious solutions. So it makes a lousy epistemic floor.

What I would like to do is to reason backwards from that pre-existing problem, justifying it by reverse-engineering its universal logical foundations, and then carry that logic forward not just to the problem, but past it, bringing it to bear on finding possible solutions. Go back, to go forward.

The backward half of the methodology is I have dubbed the Law of Radical Consensus: "Any disagreement can be reframed as a form of consensus, simply by jointly acknowledging THAT the dispute exists."

[The limit case is "we agree that we are not sure whether we disagree."]

So, we iteratively apply the LoRC until universality and consensus have converged in a handful of self-evident truths. These become our new epistemic floor.

Personally, I set that floor above the level of divinity (no possible universal agreement) and also above the level of neural mechanisms, quantum or otherwise (same reason), leaving it somewhere in the level of "simultaneous presence of several logical operators, however it is that they work."

And then, reason forward deductively from there, using the standard deductive toolkit, until we get somewhere useful.

I think it's maybe more of an engineering approach, perhaps.

Ymar Sakar said...

What i can detect of the hybrid approach us that it takes on the weaknesses of both methods but not always the strrngths.

It is a good thing human society is failing. This is part of the divine plan. From a deep state or esoteric tradition, satan rules the rulers and leaders of humanity. And societies are jist human groups that use leaders.

By clearing away the field with fire, new crops can be planted. Tjis is only a temporary cataclysm. Short term vs long term results.

Piercello said...

Ymar,

(1) The first strength of the hybrid approach is that it allows people of differing certainties to work together to achieve immediate and meaningful societal results, while also easily identifying those who can't/won't be bothered to try.

(2) The second strength of the hybrid approach is that, upon honest application to human decision-making, it deductively reveals hidden universals in that logical process. These universals can be trusted, even in this Age of Disinformation we inhabit, because their self-evident origins arise at the place where I have located my epistemic floor.

[To be clear, none of the belief-content examples you have given in these two threads have violated the belief-process universalities I have in mind, which really do apply at the logical level to all possible human decisions!

I'm sure this is entirely caused by my own terminological inadequacies, as I have not yet defined (here) in which directions I have bent the relevant definitions. My apologies.]

(3) The third strength of the hybrid approach is that, when applied at the societal level, it reveals the presence of emergent universals, logical standing waves found in the human societal fabric, that govern the rise and fall of all possible human societies.

[That is, we can quantify the BOTH the topographical highs and lows AND the natural, quasi-gravitational force that attracts society into corruption and dysfunction, without first having to determine whether or not (or in what precise framing) that force is ultimately divine; it simply IS, and its "physical" effects can be measured.

In this way I hope to escape unnecessary (and I think unwinnable) belief-content battles over the nature of divinity itself by pushing them below my epistemic floor.]

(4) And the fourth strength of the hybrid approach is that it can map the standing waves that lie hidden beneath the ideological fog, distinguishing good routes from bad in order to help us get from "here" to "there," and then also characterize the motive force that allows us to defy gravity and traverse those routes toward the desirable civilizational heights.

All of this arises from my study of human universals, not from emphasizing our real or imagined differences.

[Note that my chosen restriction, that of exclusively studying human universals, also absolves me from having to navigate the hurdles and pitfalls of statistical methodology.]

But, as you can see, a fair amount of decision-driven human resistance exists even to the idea that my approach might be possible! Humans tend to have a lot of energy invested in emphasizing our differences, and also in sticking to "us/them" pet theories of causation.

Anyway, circling back to point one, the whole idea is to find a common ground upon which societal building is possible, even though large numbers of people have already given up on that approach.

It is finding a way into the argument, getting people to buy into its possibility and potential, that is turning out to be so difficult.

To me, that is part of the enormous value of this conversation.

Piercello said...

For reference, here is my epistemic floor, with short commentary:

4. Instinct handles the basics of human life.
(Heart rate, reflexes, thirst/hunger, circadian rhythms, fight/flight reactions…)

5. Conscious attention has functional limits.
(Speed, latency, power, focus, bandwidth…)

6. Human intelligence uses patterns and mental habits as workarounds.
(Categories, associations, arguments, analogies, routines…)

Notes: In keeping with the goals of the LoRC, all terminology debates (e.g., “instinct”) are to be solved by assuming the broadest possible definitions, unless specifically noted otherwise.

Also in keeping with those goals, each of these three attributes is (1) universal in scope; (2) widely acknowledged to be true; (3) independently verifiable by self-evident observation; and (4) impossible to turn off.

THAT these three attributes exist together is sufficient in order for the following arguments to work; HOW each attribute works in isolation is unimportant.

Grim said...

I'm sorry, gentlemen, I'm 15 comments behind because I took the weekend off to play in the snow (Saturday) and the sun (Sunday). I'll need some time to catch up.

ymarsakar said...

(1) The first strength of the hybrid approach is that it allows people of differing certainties to work together to achieve immediate and meaningful societal results, while also easily identifying those who can't/won't be bothered to try.

Well, that would be more obviously true if you could put it into action with Flat Earth Theory vs Heliocentricism.

In scientific methodology, it is important to test one's data and theories and conclusions after all. If this was merely a metaphysical mental exercise in philosophy, then how could anyone test it out? But your approach says it has an impact on society. Since society is physical, we can make use of that to test it.

Grim, most of the meta points here I was able to summarize succinctly at near the end. That is because partially I didn't feel it necessary to write a counter thesis when it was Grim vs P, and not Me vs Everyone (as usual). And also partially because I don't like typing on phones.

ymarsakar said...

To be clear, none of the belief-content examples you have given in these two threads have violated the belief-process universalities I have in mind, which really do apply at the logical level to all possible human decisions!

Even if they do not violate those belief processes, it would be useful for you to test your thoughts in physical reality.

How do you know that what you believe is in actuality, applicable at the logical level to all possible human decisions if you do not deal with human decisions and physical realities?

Flat Earth Theory vs Heliocentricism is not an old and obsolete topic. High schoolers, K-12, and univesities, as well as modern scientists, have been talking about it.

All of this arises from my study of human universals, not from emphasizing our real or imagined differences.

Philosophers do not emphasize real differences. I understand that. But for those wishing to make an impact on human society, I would suggest leaning more towards scientific methodology (the real one, not the scientism religion variant).

J Peterson is a good example of someone who has academic credentials and thinks in very mystical, archetypical, abstract, non realistic fashions, but is able to resonant with real humans because he touches upon their shadow fears and insecurities. Even if his epistemological floor or ceiling is inferior to your construction, P, his impact is greater.

Piercello said...

Y, I feel the same way about phones and typing. Much respect!

I disagree with none of the criticisms you are so thoughtfully supplying. I could answer them, mostly, by unfolding my argument in full, if it were already completely written.

My problem is that I need to figure out how to _describe_ my argument, not just to make it.

This is the stage I am stuck on. Why should anyone read it?

I need to be able to introduce reasons for adopting my argument in the first place, describing both it and them in a sufficiently interesting/concise way as to entice readers into following its complexity. Because it is, unfortunately, complex.

Methodologically, in order to answer your specific questions, I would need to unfold the argument in this way:

(1) Zoom out to where universality and consensus converge in a handful of self-evident truths, establishing a robust epistemic floor;

(2) Argue inward, ensuring that universality/consensus are conserved at each step, until meaningful results are achieved (for example, I would be reframing intelligence, instinct, identity, intuition, and emotion);

(3) Summarize the universal structural and informational implications of the results to date;

(4) Characterize the emergent universal effects of those results that appear at three new levels: within individuals, between individuals, and across populations;

(5) Develop social strategies (applications) that apply across populations, between individuals, and within individuals;

(6) Summarize the whole thing for easy reference.

But none of that tells you WHY you should bother!

In a most unhelpful twist, I can tell you (from within the argument) exactly why that is the case, but not without explaining the whole thing first. I am stuck in a bit of a catch-22.

The universal logic of the human decision-making process (What is the motive energy source? Where exactly does it come from? How does it flow? How is our awareness of that flow constrained by our own limits?) operates independently of whatever content the decisions are about. That in itself has its own strategic implications. Working them out is kind of the whole point!

What elements might help me to sell you on the utility of such an approach? Specifically in the sense of a descriptive introduction?

(The logician in me wants to just leap straight into the structural intricacies, but I know that isn't persuasive.)

ymarsakar said...

If you have number 5, and some examples, then it would only require another reverse engineering and reasoning backwards to go further.

You seem to be thinking of this as a linear logic problem. Meaning before you get to the product you desire, you want to detail out the entire chain of production, or in this case the mathematical/logical proof.

That's really not necessarily for most people or those that can reverse engineer the method from the answer.

Because I know the answers to some of the things you are working out, I don't actually need the methodology itself.

ymarsakar said...

The universal logic of the human decision-making process (What is the motive energy source? Where exactly does it come from? How does it flow? How is our awareness of that flow constrained by our own limits?) operates independently of whatever content the decisions are about. That in itself has its own strategic implications. Working them out is kind of the whole point!

Yes, it would be an interesting task, but I am using cheats, so I already have most of the answers. That does not mean I used your method or another method to go backwards from human axioms, find hidden premises, and then go forwards to outline a plan or theory or thesis (I did not follow your 1-4). So even if you asked me what would be a descriptive introduction, I can only answer that I work from the conclusion backwards. The introduction is a mystery to me, because I didn't need to go there. A lot of people often times prefer doing it that way, to save time in physical reality. It's why "Executive Summary" is a thing in technical writing. If there was not that page written in the first 5 pages, then people like me would just read the last pages looking for the "gist" and why it matters first.

Rather differently, I was given the thesis/conclusion, and I worked backwards from there. That is similar to you current quest although... it is not very close. It is at least closer to your thoughts than to Grim's counter thoughts.

What elements might help me to sell you on the utility of such an approach?

In terms of utility, the scenarios I presented before still remain as options. 3:19 PM

I often take the position that human logic is unnecessary or at least erroneous, vs Grim's usage of logic.

ymarsakar said...

Which means, what Grim finds useful is very different from what I find useful.

Thus if you original point is to counter Grim's, then I am just an irrelevant outlier that does impact the logic at all.

Or in other words, perhaps you will have to wait for Grim's response.

Grim said...

You will have to wait a bit longer for it, anyway; I didn't have time today to catch up on the discussion. Hopefully tomorrow.

Piercello said...

Welcome back, Grim! Hopefully we are keeping you entertained.

Y, a few scattered responses this morning:

I _think_ what I am trying to do is shoehorn a decidedly nonlinear argument into a linear pathway, in order that those who prefer to reason in a linear fashion can manage it.

Interestingly, I came in "in the middle" myself, with an unexpected insight that united several domains of knowledge and made sense of everything else I have seen since. Whether or not that counts as a divine revelation in the sense that you have experienced, I can't be sure.

My plan is to first epistemically ground the known "middle" so that it holds water for those without the specific multi-domain knowledge I happen to have and then assemble the endgame from there.

Even in the mid-game, the kinds of conclusions I wish to draw (to the attention of others) are sufficiently sweeping and unusual that I think it is necessary to establish a _strong_ logical/evidentiary "chain of custody," which is most of why I have worked so far backwards to set my epistemic floor; but...

...at the same time, I recognize that I must also somehow incorporate a way for each reader to skip ahead to the personally relevant bits. Integrating depth and skimmability is an interesting organizational challenge! But I do have some ideas on that front as well. See the end of this comment.

And, of course, since neither of us has laid our full cards on the table, it is difficult to assess just how complementary/compatible our two frameworks might be.

Be all of that as it may, this back-and-forth with your different perspective is invaluable. It can only help me in making sense out of this whole thing.


Here is another snippet. Taken together with the "epistemic floor" snippet in an earlier comment, it should help illustrate both the direction of the argument and the organizational approach I am trying out:

21. Intelligence stores learned patterns as modular habits of thought and action, making them fast, efficient, and invisible.
(Reading these words is easy. You weren’t even noticing the letters inside the words. Or the font! Until just now.)

22. The machinery of habit continuously stacks and restacks these modules, with or without conscious direction.
(How long until you finally noticed that your new commute was already driving itself? Habits evolve.)

23. By definition, limited attention builds *local* habits, which tend to fail unpredictably in non-local conditions.
(Every music student: “I swear, I could play that passage perfectly at home!”)

24. Limited attention also prevents us from ever rationally integrating ALL of our locally effective habits at once.
(Your mind’s eye surfs an evolving, invisible tangle of associations, analogies, and reasoned connections. But which is which?)

25. Instead, we just switch mental gears, jumping from stack to modular stack, in search of better real-world results.
(Driving in traffic, in rain, at night, on the highway, while late for work... Different scenarios call up different local habits.)

Ymar Sakar said...

The recent stock market dip, crash, rise, crash, dip, is interesting on more than economic profit. I gave some free market advice when raven said on thursday or friday about off loading allinvestments.

People cannot time the markets reliably. Except some have my systemic knowledge. I said one last dip on monday before crash end of gov, due to pluto in capricorn.

People may not know this but tesla and jan 2020 perpetual rally could easily be prediced using vedic astrology.

So market trading has human emotions but also logic and numbers.

A lot of what you mentioned is referred to in other fields as ego self, natural habitual instincts, environment, dna, etc.

To illustrate my method, is to lnow that even though i knew it was a mini bubble in jan, i only did my normal trading method
I did not deviate. I had the timing of crash down to the exact day even, but after monday, i had not studied the star transits so undrrestimated human fear. So i traded the dip well enough but timed it a bit too soon after, forcing a few days of temporary unintended effects.

If i had control of millions... it would have been a 5 to 15% gain. This stuff is almost too easy. Which is where the saying comes that millionaires dont use astrology, billionares and reagan do.

Grim said...

By my lights, ANY such terminological convention, whether one is born into it or adopts in for practical reasons (such as easier communication with an established discipline), is by nature a pre-existing rhetorical consensus, in which the terminological battles have already been fought and settled.

This is a very Kantian move. I'm thinking that the crucial distinction is between whether "man is the measure of all things," as Protagoras said, or if that is not so, as Socrates said. Protagoras would have us believe that everything is social convention, more or less; Socrates thought that some things were higher matters that humans could not alter. My suggestion is that rhetoric is the kind of thing that man measures, but mathematics is one of the things that we do not measure: even though we may invent a rhetorical convention like base 3 or base 4, either way the quality of that rhetoric is testable against the objective facts that govern mathematics. Some math cannot be made to work, even in theory, because it is wrong. That's not rhetoric, and it is certainly not based on our consensus about it. That fact is prior to our consensus, and has priority over it.

In most things we call rhetoric, consensus may be all there is. But not everything, and that's the core division I see.

So the first step may be to determine which of the two cases you are in: one in which man is the measure, and consensus is therefore the ground for all discussion -- that is the case you're describing, and the way you talk about it it seems as if you think that might be the only case that there is. If so, you side with Protagoras (and might want to read the dialogue that bears his name).

But if you agree that there are at least some cases in which man is not the measure, but rather will have his systems measured against something else that is objective in the world, you'll need to distinguish those cases. Then the question is not one of mapping out where we agree, but of sorting out which of our disagreements is the kind of disagreement that admits of tests. You might wish to say: "But even to have that discussion, we need to have a consensus about the terms." Yet I don't think so; these sorts of things are often very practical matters, like how many of these things here there are, in which it is sufficient to directly reference the things rather than to build a system for describing them.

Anonymous said...

Hmmm.

I'm still not sold on there being a "bright line" distinction between logic and rhetoric. There may be something more fractal going on.

For example, I would say that the clear "logic" part has to do with rationally mappable interactions of known human similarities, known ways in which we are all already demonstrably alike, and which persist whether or not any rhetorical framing bound by social convention is in place.

At the same time, that bright-line logic contains within it the necessity for human beings to couch its operations in rhetorical terms, in order to communicate with other people as they map its rigorous but intricate structure.

That logic also contains bright-line explanations for the rhetorical tendency for people to talk past one another, and to defend their own emotionally invested rhetorical positions well past the bounds of reasoned debate.

And without enough of a rhetorical consensus, we won't be able to talk intelligibly about the bright-line logic.

So it IS a bright-line logic that interests me, a fixed, rule-based state of affairs, but it is one that both requires a shared rhetorical framing to talk about, and also sets forth the universal logical rules by which that rhetorical requirement comes into being. And that pulls me into rhetorical interests as well.

The universality of our logical rules of process is what necessarily produces the individual uniqueness of our rhetorical content, both in terms of what is already believed, and in terms of what will/will not be persuasive.

Which of course is what makes the seeking of rhetorical consensus difficult. But we need at least enough of a shared rhetorical solution, if we are ever to get around to unveiling the bright-line logic.

This entanglement is what makes it hard for me to see the rhetorical/logical switch as either/or.

But again, it is likely that we are still talking past one another!

Y is right, typing on phones is awful.

Piercello said...

But, as far as getting on the same rhetorical page goes,

It may work, in this specific case, to take the opposite route of standard academic writing.

Rather than using narrow, precise definitions, it may be sufficient (to map the underlying logic) to use broad accuracy instead. If the logical structures are as persistent as I think they are, that should work.

If we could agree THAT a universal logical basis for our disagreements might exist, and then go on to map out generally what it is within a broad rhetorical consensus, then that could give an interesting strategic insight into how those problems might be solved (or at least better engineered around, as unchangeable constraints).

But since the nature of such a universal logic is abstract, it is perhaps more dependent on rhetorical consensus than some other topics.

The real prize is the logic. BUT, the path to understanding how it works is rhetorical.

I think.