Nicomachean Ethics I.11

A quite short section today.
That the fortunes of descendants and of all a man's friends should not affect his happiness at all seems a very unfriendly doctrine, and one opposed to the opinions men hold; but since the events that happen are numerous and admit of all sorts of difference, and some come more near to us and others less so, it seems a long- nay, an infinite- task to discuss each in detail; a general outline will perhaps suffice.

It is strange to see the philosopher weigh in against a doctrine as being "unfriendly." That is also how Terence Irwin gives it, though, in his translation. In the Greek original it is ἄφιλον, which is usually 'friendless' rather than 'unfriendly,' but I trust either of these translators' Greek more than my own very limited Greek. Harris Rackham's translation gives it as "heartless." 

In any case it's not a proof or a logical argument; it's a sense that the doctrine isn't desirable and that it is widely rejected and without popularity. That doesn't mean it isn't true.

If, then, as some of a man's own misadventures have a certain weight and influence on life while others are, as it were, lighter, so too there are differences among the misadventures of our friends taken as a whole, and it makes a difference whether the various suffering befall the living or the dead (much more even than whether lawless and terrible deeds are presupposed in a tragedy or done on the stage), this difference also must be taken into account; or rather, perhaps, the fact that doubt is felt whether the dead share in any good or evil.

That sentence could use some analysis. If some misadventures have more or less weight than others, then also our friends' misadventures may be more or less important to them. Also, it seems to Aristotle that it matters whether the misfortunes happen to a living or a dead man. 

That's sensible enough. It would bother almost anyone if a financial disaster befell them that cost them literally everything they own; but every dead man immediately yields up all his worldly goods, and seems not to suffer from it much at all. The ancients sometimes buried men and women with grave goods, but not all of their goods; and even in the famous Viking funeral sequence recorded by Ibn Fadhlan at least some was left to the inheritance. 

Aristotle says that this living/dead distinction is even more important than the truth/fiction distinction: a dead man seems to suffer less than a fictional one from the loss of his goods, say. So perhaps the dead do not suffer any evil, or any good. That was the unfriendly doctrine. It might be true. 

For it seems, from these considerations, that even if anything whether good or evil penetrates to them, it must be something weak and negligible, either in itself or for them, or if not, at least it must be such in degree and kind as not to make happy those who are not happy nor to take away their blessedness from those who are. The good or bad fortunes of friends, then, seem to have some effects on the dead, but effects of such a kind and degree as neither to make the happy unhappy nor to produce any other change of the kind.
Aristotle ends on some middle ground. There is something about the fortune of friends or descendants that might affect the dead; but it can't be very strong. The blessed remain blessed; the unhappy dead cannot be made happy by us afterwards, no matter what we try to do.

This seems consistent with much of later theology, although the Church has sold pardons and indulgences at times, and many a man has donated in the hope of Masses sung for the repose of his soul. It is doubtful that these do much good; but why not hedge your bets? 

5 comments:

Thomas Doubting said...

seems a very unfriendly doctrine

Bartlett and Collins translate this as: "appears to be excessively opposed to what is dear," with a footnote that offers "excessively unfriendly" or "hateful" as alternatives.

Thomas Doubting said...

Something interesting for a bit now is that we don't seem to be talking about excellence anymore. If happiness is an action, what does that have to do with whether family and friends are successful? Or whether the dead can be made more or less happy? This seems like it should be in a discussion of honor or reputation or something. It seems that happiness is, in fact, not just a form of excellence or activity, but that there is a social aspect to it and something that is beyond our control.

Thomas Doubting said...

As for the dead, in Catholic theology, don't prayers help those in Purgatory?

I talked about prayers for the dead with an Orthodox priest once who said that, theologically, prayers always do some good, so it was his opinion that even for a damned soul a prayer must relieve some of the suffering. Just his opinion, of course, but it seems reasonable.

Grim said...

So, it is a bit strange to be discussing the dead here. Aristotle got here because he wanted to assert that happiness is fullest in a complete life; but now he has the problem that the most complete life is one that is over. So now he is asking, what about that?

A metaphysical problem for him is his potential/actual distinction. Potentiality is first actuality, but he views the actual as better and fuller than the merely potential. Yet once something is fully actual, it no longer has potential.

So if you have led a fully actual happy life, it’s over. You’re no longer potentially happy. You have, to put it another way, no more potential for happiness.

It’s a troubling conclusion and I am not surprised that he is worried about it. He’s being honest but he doesn’t quite want to admit the hateful conclusion.

Grim said...

I have heard that they do, and I once purchased an indulgence for the soul of my grandfather (the one who was most like me, and therefore most likely to need one). I pray for the dead. Perhaps it makes them happier. I don’t think it can hurt, anyway.